Is philosophy just a lot of hot air,
or is there more to it than that? Are philosophers just good at
creating problems, but not at solving them? Can philosophers be
useful to epidemiologists? Put another way, should epidemiologists
care about philosophy?
Alex Broadbent,
a young British-trained philosopher of science with a faculty
appointment at the University of Johannesburg, clearly believes in
the potential value of philosophy for epidemiology, and has set
out to prove it. His forays into the field are now evident from
the work he has published as guest editor of a themed-section of
peer-reviewed essays in Preventive Medicine on Philosophy and
Epidemiology, to which eminent figures from epidemiology and
statistics as well as philosophy contributed, and as principal
author of a new report from the PHG foundation entitled
“Epidemiology, risk, and causation—Conceptual and methodological
issues in public health science”.
These publications are not solo
contributions but rather the products of a series of workshops
which Broadbent helped to organize in 2009-10 on Epidemiology,
Risk, and Genomics hosted at the University of Cambridge,
Department of History and Philosophy of Science and sponsored by
the PHG Foundation. He has also organized an international
conference on the topic in December 2011, with funds from the
South African government.
Doubts About Philosophy
In the introduction to his PHG
report, Broadbent is candid about the skepticism which he believes
may confront his endeavors in the epidemiology community. He
states, “Doubt is often expressed when philosophers purport to
contribute to the scientific enterprise…Epidemiology is a useful
activity, and there is ample evidence in epidemiological journals
and text books that philosophical problems arise in the course of
doing it. The motivation of this project was to identify some of
these problems, and to begin the process of solving them.”
Philosophical Problems
Before enumerating the problems of
interest in epidemiology, Broadbent was asked to clarify what
constitutes a philosophical problem. He told the Epidemiology
Monitor that such problems are those which people disagree about,
where the disagreements are persistent yet reasonable, and for
which further empirical evidence will not get you an answer. He
stated that ethical problems are a type of philosophical problem
that are easier to recognize than other types because we have
pre-existing ideas about right and wrong.
According to Broadbent, where
concepts such as causation, risk, uncertainty, and causal
inference have seemed too vague to use, epidemiologists have
developed well-defined substitutes. However, it is not always
clear how to relate these well-defined concepts back to the vague
ones in which we think when deciding on courses of action or
making evaluative judgments. Moreover, inconsistencies in our
innate, “Stone Age” thinking are often brought out when
epidemiologists seek to apply and extend the Stone Age concepts.
Evidence cannot be brought to bear to resolve the difficulties,
which are conceptual. It is in these areas where a philosophical
approach could be helpful.
Philosophers Training
If philosophical problems have no
definite solutions, why should philosophers be expected to be more
helpful than epidemiologists? According to Broadbent, philosophers
are trained in tackling such questions and have skills which
better enable them to identify the problems to begin with, make
distinctions, and clarify them. Given these skills, philosophers
may not settle issues definitively, however, their approach can
help “to close down some options and avoid inconsistencies,” says
Broadbent.
Epidemiologists Not Trained
Broadbent told the Epidemiology
Monitor that he has observed epidemiologists struggling with
thorny philosophical issues in epidemiology. In one case, he
observed an epidemiologist author taking a very authoritarian
approach to explaining causation, asserting “this is how it is”.
Philosophers would take a completely different approach, said
Broadbent, a non-authoritarian, more exploratory one in which
coherent options or alternatives are identified and discussed. For
these types of questions which may not have a final answer, this
is “a better approach” according to Broadbent.
Hitting Too Hard
Broadbent contrasts the
philosophical approach with the one taken by scientists in yet
another way. “Scientists tend to hit these problems too hard,”
according to Broadbent, “closing off options and moving on when it
is too soon to close options down without really understanding the
position you are taking.” He added that, in contrast to
scientists, philosophers are not typically trying “to get on with
something”.
Philosophy can pay off for epidemiology in a number of ways: by
reducing methodological inconsistencies, raising awareness of
methodological error, making epidemiological concepts more useful,
and making epidemiological evidence and arguments more compelling
to a non-epidemiological audience, such as health policy makers or
courts of law.
An Example
As an example of how philosophical
thinking can be useful to epidemiology, Broadbent cited the topic
of prediction. He said that philosophers have not given a lot of
thought to what makes a good prediction as they have for what
makes for a good causal inference. How to assess a predictive
claim is a philosophical problem, but one which would have
practical value for epidemiologists, according to Broadbent.
His paper published in Preventive
Medicine creates a heuristic—having to explain “what could
possibly go wrong”—to achieve a robust prediction about the
outcomes of a health intervention in the real world (as opposed to
in a study population). Just as Bradford Hill’s heuristic
for causal inference is helpful for that function, so Broadbent is
hoping his heuristic for prediction will have practical value.
As another example, he has also
recently published an article making detailed recommendations on
the use of epidemiological evidence to prove causation in law.
Philosophical Topics
Based on the discussions at the
workshops he has helped organize, Broadbent has developed a
preliminary list of topics which have either practical or
philosophical significance and which could benefit from further
philosophical work. They are:
1. The need for conceptual clarity
in the use of health statistics
2. The need for clarity in the use
of statistical significance testing in particular
3. The difficulty of causal
inference and its continued resistance to formal methods.
4. The importance of distinguishing
between internal and external validity and the difficulties of
applying study results to a wider group
5. Continued methodological
development in epidemiology as a young science
6. Understanding the live
methodological and conceptual debates within the discipline
7. The complexity of the sorts of
claims epidemiology makes about general causation
8. The paradox of prevention
9. Reconsideration of philosophic
views of science in light of unique features of epidemiology as a
science.
10. The need for a philosophy of
epidemiology within the philosophy of science.
Final Word
Broadbent told the Epidemiology
Monitor that the need for a philosophy of epidemiology is the sign
of a growing and maturing discipline with an increasing impact on
society. When asked what response he would like to obtain to his
work from the epidemiology community, Broadbent said it would be
beneficial if epidemiologists could be more accepting of the types
of problems he is seeking to identify. He understands that
epidemiologists might not always be inclined to spend precious
time discussing problems that “you cannot shut down with a sharp
answer”. According to Broadbent, the existence of philosophical
problems in epidemiology is not a sign of weakness, but a
corollary of the maturing and conceptual development of the
discipline. They are a sign of the difficulty the human mind has
of getting a hold of the concepts epidemiologists use and the
phenomena they study. It would be beneficial for epidemiologists
to be open to the possibility that a philosophy of epidemiology
could be useful, says Broadbent.
Another view, not intended to be
critical of epidemiologists, is that epidemiologists should not
rely solely on other epidemiologists to resolve these
philosophical questions. There is a tendency in every field for
senior scientists to wade into the philosophy pool, according to
Broadbent, but some papers on philosophical topics by senior
epidemiologists are “just not good”, he said.
Metaphors
He told the Epi Monitor he does not
intend his remarks to be belligerent, but simply a call for
epidemiologists to recognize the expertise of others in this
domain. “You don’t expect birds to be good ornithologists,” said
Broadbent, and scientists should not expect to be good
philosophers of science, any more than philosophers of science can
expect to be good scientists. It is difficult for persons to avoid
producing just hot air on these types of problems, according to
Broadbent. You have to stop yourself. It is hard. Recognizing that
philosophers have relevant skills and training, would be a useful,
according to Broadbent.
Links to a free download of the PHG
report and to the relevant issue of Preventive Medicine are
provided below.
Also, read two related articles on
the Philosophy of Epidemiology in this issue.
http://www.phgfoundation.org/reports/10491/
http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/00917435
|